Thursday, April 8, 2010

Against the Great Books?


The Great Books are not the solution to the problems of higher education in this country. In fact, the Great Books are enemies of wisdom.

How could a proud graduate of the University of Dallas like myself say such a thing? Such a statement practically amounts to blasphemy!

But, before you dismiss me as some crazy liberal, let me point out that I am not the one who made those statements. They were made by Patrick Deneen and Fritz Wilhelmsen--hardly crazy liberals. If anything, they are usually described as crazy conservatives. And indeed, both men make their critique of Great Books programs from a conservative perspective. Last week Deneen wrote an article "Why the Great Books Aren't the Answer" which has sparked some lively discussion on a couple Internet forums. Deneen's concerns, though, are not entirely original; they were voiced years ago by one of UD's very own, the late Fritz Wilhelmsen, in his essay "The Great Books: Enemies of Wisdom."

There is a lot to think about in Deneen's and Wilhelmsen's articles, but I would like to focus on one interesting issue they both raise, and one which is, I believe, at the heart of their critique of Great Books programs: the role of tradition in a proper education.

Deneen identifies two potential effects that Great Books programs will have on most students. On the one hand, making students read a "potpourri of conflicting views"--from the ancient Greeks through the 20th century--can easily lead a student to adopt relativism or to despair of ever finding the truth once he realizes that all the great thinkers he has read disagreed radically with one another. On the other hand, many students enter college with a progressive theory of history in their mind: all of history has reached its culmination in the present, therefore the present is the best. Instead of relativism, these students will simply be confirmed in progressivist dogma. But more worrisome than either relativism or progressivism by itself is the possibility that students will combine these twin dangers of relativism to form a single monster: the dogmatic relativist. The dogmatic relativist will believe that history, and therefore truth, has culminated in relativism.

To fend off these dangers, universities, in Deneen's view, need to give students a framework within which to read the Great Books, and not simply approach them with neutrality. Ultimately, Deneen (a professor at Georgetown) believes it is necessary to teach "in the light of the standards that the Catholic tradition would provide."

Wilhelmsen in his article focuses less on the conflicting content of the Great Books and more on the inadequacy of the Great Books in fostering in students the virtues necessary for the philosophical life. For Wilhelmsen, following Aristotle, philosophy is a way of knowing; it is not found in books, but rather in the philosopher's virtues, the habits of the mind, "through which things are understood in their causal structures." Philosophy, though, also requires that a master educate a beginner in these virtues. This approach to philosophy--which Wilhelmsen describes as it used to be practiced in Catholic universities in America--is at once both traditional and personal. Each student (and teacher) submits to the tradition, but is also able, thanks to his own virtues, to contribute to that tradition. Wilhelmsen at one point even uses the word "apprentice" to describe a student's relationship to his teacher. A philosophy department at a university, then, should in this respect quite literally resemble a craft guild.

For Wilhelmsen, one of the chief follies of the typical Great Books program, besides only teaching students what others said rather than to philosophize themselves, is to teach certain texts with no regard for the historical context in which they were written. Students are expected to cope with the most varied authors "without having the faintest hint of the kind of world within which these men lived and thought." In other words, the typical Great Books program utterly neglects the importance of tradition.

Deneen's and Wilhelmsen's critiques of Great Books programs, though they emphasize different aspects of education, both rest on the assumption that a student cannot learn the truth unless he is embedded within a craft and a tradition.

This insight that has been developed by Alisdair MacIntyre in the area of virtue ethics, especially in Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and Tradition (in particular, chapter III: “Too Many Thomisms?”) According to MacIntyre, tradition embodies the claim that “reason can only move towards being genuinely universal and impersonal insofar as it is neither neutral nor disinterested, that membership in a particular type of moral community, one from which fundamental dissent has to be excluded, is a condition for genuinely rational enquiry and more especially for moral and theological enquiry.” This claim would sound preposterous to most people today, especially in a discussion of higher education, since most people conceive of higher education as “free enquiry." MacIntyre, however, defends the rationality of tradition by pointing to two things an apprentice in any craft has to learn:

[First,] the apprentice has to learn, at first from his or her teachers and then in his or her continuing self-education, how to identify mistakes made by him or herself in applying the acknowledged standards, the standards recognized to be the best available so far in the history of that particular craft…[Second,] the apprentice has to learn to distinguish between the kind of excellence which both others and he or she can expect of him or herself here and now and that ultimate excellence which furnishes both apprentices and mastercraftsmen with their telos.
But, how does an individual’s membership in a craft connect with a larger historical tradition? “The standards of achievement within any craft are justified historically. They have emerged from the criticism of their predecessors and they are justified because and insofar as they have remedied the defects and transcended the limitations of those predecessors as guides to excellent achievement within that particular craft.”

To conclude before I quote the entirety of Three Rival Versions, I would like not to provide a complete justification of tradition--that would require me to write books I am not capable of writing--but simply to draw out three implications which Deneen, Wilhelmsen, and MacIntyre's position has for higher education, particularly Catholic higher education.

First, we must take the historical aspect of learning within a tradition much more seriously than we do now. Many of the problematic aspects of a Great Books program arise from false philosophies of history--especially, as Deneen notes, relativism and progressivism. The solution is a proper understanding of education as initiation into a craft, into a tradition. And a tradition's standards, as MacIntyre reminds us, are justified historically.

Second, if we want to restore this understanding of education as initiation into a craft, we cannot make students fumble in the dark reading all the Great Books yet expect them somehow to figure out how to philosophize on their own. And realistically, we cannot expect students to find their own way into the tradition in the four short years of their undergraduate education. College is, in many cases, already a late stage to enter into a tradition. This means we have a lot of work to do in restoring the educational craft, not only at the university level, but also in high schools, and even in elementary schools.

Third, if any healthy tradition necessarily excludes fundamental dissent in order to teach students to philosophize, we have to radically rethink our notion of academic freedom. More specifically, we have to rethink the relationship of education and religion. Academic freedom today is often portrayed as the freedom to ignore or even disparage religion. But academic freedom is not the freedom to mock what is holy, or even to read the Great Books; academic freedom--as Wilhelmsen explains--is really the freedom of a craftsman working in a tradition.


Note: For further comments on Deneen's article, see Front Porch Republic and First Things.

16 comments:

Jeremy M said...

This is a great critique of a curriculum based on the "Great Books", and I couldn't agree more. However, I also think that UD has been a place where there has been an attempt to "fit the tradition into a framework". Has it been completely successful? Probably not, but UD has probably fallen into error on this point LESS than most places. So to idolize OR castigate it are each non-productive.

Paul said...

I'm not persuaded... All the critiques made here about Great Books programs could be made about state of education in general. At least with Great Books the source material is worthwhile.

I suspect too that some criticism of Great Books programs as 'progressivist' or 'relativist" is born out of 'conservative' xenophobia--these same critics will short change Nietzsche, etc., and so is it any wonder that they're not thrilled with Great Books?

The danger on the other side is that education be made into some sort of indoctrination into establishment ideologies... again, I do not wonder that some conservatives want this.

Finally, college is by no means too late to be brought into a tradition. I note the qualification "in many cases" but think the emphasis should be not on what is impossible for some in college but rather what is possible for many.

Stephen said...

Jeremy,

Thank you for the compliment. I actually agree with you that UD does a good job of providing a framework. I should have made that clear.

Stephen said...

Paul,

You say that all these critiques apply to the state of education in general. But, that's the point: Great Books programs in many ways suffer from the same problems as higher education in general, and that's why they don't necessarily fix anything. That's why Deneen's article is called "Why the Great Books aren't the answer."

As for conservative indoctrination, I think you invoke something of a bogey-man. All education has elements of indoctrination, because all education involves learning of doctrine. Life is not impossible without some shared basis of discussion. But, a real tradition--if you read MacIntyre--allows for development; in fact, the success of a tradition depends on its ability to teach students to identify and correct mistakes.

For a good discussion of the importance of tradition in education (theology in particular), I recommend R.R. Reno's article in the May 2007 issue of First Things, "Theology after the Revolution."

Paul said...

Stephen,

Oh, I appreciate the importance of tradition--one of the reasons I favor the Great Books. And tradition must develop or it's not living, but dead. So I'm with you on all that... I do not think however that the 'solution' being presented by those who criticize the Great Books programs is much of a solution, but rather plays too much off a tendency to dichotomize everything into tidy categories.

Sure, with Great Books, someone might read Nietzsche and conclude he's right on this or that, and someone else might conclude the opposite. Worse though, I think, is reading Nietzsche from a starting point that says he's wrong--studying him just to refute him. That sort of education is not education at all.

Indoctrination is not always a bad thing as such, but when it's directing one into ignorance, that's a problem. Maybe that's not really indoctrination at that point, but would be better described as brainwashing.

Maybe, in the end, there's more agreement here than I first supposed. I do not think Great Books programs are necessarily superior to others. I do think though that the curricula of most programs would be improved by including at least some texts which are enduring, instead of mere pop trash novelties.

Aaron Linderman said...

Is strikes me that KU's defunct (but legendary) Integrated Humanities Program sought to return to an initiation into a craft and a tradition, rather than plowing through context-less (though admittedly great) books.

They learned the constellations in astronomy class, studied penmanship, learned ballroom dance and listened to folks in rural Ireland tell stories around the fire. One class involved students simply listening to two professors discuss a philosophic question. No notes were taken, nor tests given. It was simply a chance to see two people have an intelligent conversation, a lost art in the modern age.

I'm sure some of the IHP's schemes ended up just being silly, or nostalgic, or even counterproductive. But it seems to me there was a real effort to initiate students in a living tradition.

Stephen said...

Paul,

I'll agree with you that it's not productive to read an author merely in order to refute him. But, what do we mean by "productive"?

Now, I'll try to give a quick answer, but my answer here is simply provisional. By "productive" I mean that an author advances the conversation in some way, by making us understand better the questions to which the tradition is seeking answers. Sometimes, of course, an author makes an important contribution to the conversation by reframing the questions that are asked--by making us see our goal clearer, and perhaps even helping us see a way to get to our goal.

So, when we read someone like Nietzsche, for example, it's good to read him if he actually says something relevant to the goal of our conversation. My (admittedly amateur) opinion of Nietzsche is that he does pose important questions about modern atheism, but that he tends to get a little sloppy in his logic. His contribution to that extent is limited, but he's also been influential because of his emotional resonance with readers, and that emotional resonance needs to be investigated. So, it's not necessarily bad to read Nietzsche, but I also think it might be necessary to be open with students about his limitations--rather than just presenting him all by himself, without any kind of interpretive framework.

Hope that helps.

Stephen said...

Aaron, you raise a good question: How do we distinguish between legitimately trying to reclaim a tradition and mere nostalgia?

Jeremy M said...

Are you both really saying "it's not productive to read an author to refute him"? I'm playing the devil's advocate a bit here, but aren't there many authors, from the Greeks to Nietzsche, that arrive at conclusions that we would heartily disagree with? That we NEED to refute?

Certainly we shouldn't suppress reason. But do I "set my Christianity aside" while reading Nietzsche? How could I? But I am forced to examine and defend my worldview in light of his claims. If I mature, I use these writers to come to a BETTER understanding of my own worldview.

So I'm uncomfortable with a view of education that implies some kind of "blank slate" or "true neutrality", as if you could start out neutral about topics that people like Nietzsche might bring up. But I don't want to IGNORE him or dismiss him, by any means.

I mean, when you really get down to it, what's the difference between "tradition" and "establishment ideologies" anyway?

Aaron Linderman said...

I think it's von Balthasar who describes heresy as the scaffolding surrounding a great church that's being built. The scaffolding is useful in the work of construction, but in the end is torn down, and should be, to reveal the beauty of the structure. Someone who confused the scaffolding with the church itself would be sadly mistaken...

Why do we read Arius? (1) To ponder the new Christological questions he has raised, for which we should thank him. (2) I would even go so far as to say that we should thank him for pointing to the mystery of procession (even if, to poor Arius, this was a problem to be avoided, rather than a mystery to be revered). (3) To expose Arius' errors, lest we fall into them. (4) To continue the conversation (ala Athanasius) when Arius comes up short.

I think we could say the same about a more revered source, such as Thomas. We read him for the interesting questions he poses, the insights he has into those questions, the stumbling blocks and errors he encounters along the way, and the ongoing conversation we can have as a result of his offerings.

Paul said...

Steven,

Your definition of 'productive' works fine for the present conversation... I would probably prefer to say rather that the question is whether reading such and such under the aspect of such and such is beneficial. I mean this broadly though--yes, are we advancing the discussion, but more importantly, are we realizing and promoting truth, beauty and goodness?

My view of Nietzsche is a little different and fits nicely with Aaron's suggestion that even heresies are scaffolding. I would never suggest that Nietzsche is perfect, and of course, as a Catholic, I necessarily find some of his conclusions to be in error. I'm not sure I agree with the idea that a teacher should present Nietzsche in terms of his limitations--it depends on the teacher really, how the limitations are presented, what the supposed limitations are, etc. The risk of presenting a text in the context of its failings is that students will not be fully open to it and will not learn all they could, especially if the teacher is mistaken. The risks of presenting text on a neutral footing is that students might actually be left to fall into a range of errors, including especially relativism. So I see a need for real prudence on the part of the teacher. If I were teaching Nietzsche at a Catholic school where the students are already assuming he's just a nasty atheist who gets things wrong, I would go out of my way to show all the stuff Nietzsche gets right. If I were presenting Nietzsche to students who were themselves tending towards atheism, I would emphasize how Nietzsche diagnoses some very serious and real problems (play off the emotional resonance you mention) but then push students to take his ideas to their full logical conclusions and highlight the resulting discord. That is, I would want to make sure they fully understand the consequences of those ideas and put them in the context of alternatives.

I tend to raise Nietzsche as an example because I think, on the whole, most Catholic thinkers greatly underestimate how much he gets right and how much good there is in his thought. Too many are too quick to simply dismiss him. (cf., Jean-Luc Marion, esp. in "God without Being", where he relies heavily on Nietzsche and Heidegger to expose the problem of describing God in terms of metaphysics.)

Jeremy, I would agree that there is much that needs to be refuted. It's essential first to understand however what exactly is being refuted. Students need to know why such and such thinks such and such. The emotional resonance that Steven mentions is key--although that might be to define the phenomena too narrowly. People will say for example how much Marx got wrong and eagerly try to refute him. That's fine as far as it goes, but at some point we should grapple with the fact that so many people have been influenced by him and accept his ideas and pose the question, why is that? If people are still persuaded by Marx, then either there is some good in him that those opposing him have overlooked, or there is still some problem, stumbling block, that trips people up and we should thoughtfully explore its nature and how best to address it.

Aaron, you hit the nail on the head.

Stephen said...

Jeremy,

I think we basically agree about how to teach an author like Nietzsche. We can't dismiss him out of hand (i.e., we shouldn't "read him merely to refute him"), but we do need to refute him. I said that a teacher should be clear about his limitations--in other words, we should be open to what is good, but also not hesitate to refute what needs to be refuted.

Stephen said...

Paul,

I think your most important point is the need for prudence on the part of the teacher. That's the essence of a traditional craft approach toward learning. It's not all up to the student to learn by himself by reading random books, but it depends on the teacher presenting the material to do so properly.

On a related note, I think that one of the serious weaknesses of the Great Books approach is that today we tend to forget that reading is not always a positive influence on the reader, and indeed can be dangerous for the reader.

Clare Krishan said...

Instead of "productive" or "beneficial" (which are both utilitarian in their metaphysical-rhetorical bent) how about "fruitful"? Shit happens, yet guano is the fertilizer of choice in all societies that move beyond hunter-gatherer status.

The issue isn't greatness per se, but POWER - what is greatness good for - and GLORY - what is goodness good for? Feelings are neither right nor wrong pace Aquinas. Development from naif sensory perception to higher levels of integrated experiential judgment is a senescence function, not a mere line between two data points. A human begins senescence at conception. Our parents accelerate that process by their poor choices in favor of power (abort the weak in favor of the strong) or extenuate it by good decisions in favor of glory (life is a social good, pursued in intercourse with others). Consider the kiddies in this London school

www.fulhamprep.co.uk/videos/Final4.swf

debating "POWER" in elementary school philosophy class (closing out "Academics" segment at c. 5 mins)

These kids will have access to the means to pursue greatness, they will be the elite power structure of our generation's senescence. But we will "benefit" only if they have been habituated in goodness. They will learn how to pursue power in school but we will only attain goodness if they "know" courtesy from their family relations, ie their habits of social intercourse that dissuade them from choosing to eliminate the weak (us, in our dotage) in favor of the strong (them, and their ability to discern a preference for satisfying an appetite for fruitfulness vs their preference for satisfying an appetite for productiveness)

Stephen said...

The Humanities Department at Villanova University has constructed a curriculum that is not a Great Books program but rather a "Great Topics" program (my term). The four core courses are "God," "Person," "Society," and "World."

For a description of Villanova's program, and for a critique of Great Books programs from James Matthew Wilson, a professor in Villanova's Humanities Department, see this interview. I recommend the entire interview, but pp. 9-13 are the most relevant to the Great Books debate.

Aaron Linderman said...

A few favorite passages from the interview:

"To read The Critique of Pure Reason alongside, say, some questions from Thomas Aquinas’ De Veritate does not necessarily lead the students arrive at an understanding of what Truth is. It just lets them know what these two supposedly great men had to say."

"I would see the Great Books telos of the human person as being simply the creation of persons who can ask important questions. That’s all right, and indeed may exhaust the imagination of most people, but it is clear that the end or purpose of human life is not simply to ask questions about things."

"If Catholic Studies risks reducing Revelation to culture, Great Books programs may risk reducing arguments about truth to a kind of dramatic poetry with authors rather than answers at the center."